It is useless to attempt to reason a man out of a thing he was never reasoned into. -Attributed to Jonathan Swift
This is my 100th post, and since I am, by training and inclination, an epistemologist, I thought it only fitting that I do a little philosophy. Here goes.
Knowledge is widely accepted to involve belief as a component. Belief is widely accepted to involve some sort of assignment of high probability as a component. Consider, however, this utterance:
[U] "I know that there are other women out there with whom I could be happy, nevertheless I still believe that she is the only one with whom I could be happy."
We can, I think, easily imagine someone reasonably making such a claim as [U]. This, however, causes problems for the widely accepted views of those concepts of knowledge and belief canvassed above.
If knowledge involves belief, then the claim above would involve its speaker in flat contradiction -- the speaker would be stating, among other things, that he believes that there are others with whom he could be happy and that there are no others with whom he could be happy.
The common strategy for dealing with such utterances is to claim that they involve a non-standard notion of knowledge -- not the philosophical notion of warranted true belief, but perhaps simply a notion involving a high degree of certainty. This however, also seems problematic.
As we noted above, belief generally is seen to involve an assignment of high probability. But on the high-degree-of-certainty reading of knowledge in the utterance above, this would involve interpreting the speaker as claiming that he has assigns a high probability both to the claim that there are others with whom he could be happy and that there are no others with whom he could be happy -- indeed, presumably, that he assigns a higher probability to the former than to the latter. However, it would seem to violate rationality norms on belief were one reasonably to be able to believe a proposition despite assigning a higher probability to another proposition that one knew to be incompatible with one's belief.
The solution I think I favor is this. The notion of belief involved in the utterance above is simply that of the proposition on which one is disposed to act. That is, what the speaker is saying in uttering [U] is that, despite the fact that he knows that there are others with whom he could be happy, nevertheless he is disposed to act as if the opposite were the case -- waiting on the object of his affection, being absolutely incapable of even considering other options, acting, in other words, however it is that the poets require.
Even this explanation of the reasonableness of uttering [U], however, would require further refinement. For presumably, betting is a form of action. But we could imagine that our speaker would, if offered a wager, bet against there being no other person with whom he could be happy, and bet on there being others with whom he could be happy, despite the fact that his other, non-betting, behavior would not reflect those probability assignments -- despite the fact, even, that he could be painfully aware that his other behavior would not reflect those betting assignments.
The upshot of all of this, the big news-flash for my 100th post, would seem to be this: reason is the servant of the passions. Whether that is something that the poets require, it certainly can't hurt when it comes to winning them readers.
Recent Comments